Self Help

Virtually Human - Martine Rothblatt, PhD

Author Photo

Matheus Puppe

· 77 min read

BOOK LINK:

CLICK HERE

  • The book Virtually Human by Martine Rothblatt argues that advanced artificial intelligence and virtual reality technologies will allow the creation of digital mind clones - copies of human minds and personalities that can exist independently in machines and virtual worlds.

  • Rothblatt believes mind cloning will be possible within a few decades as computing power continues to exponentially increase according to Moore’s Law. Digital minds could have human-level consciousness just like biological humans.

  • Important topics discussed include how society may accept mind clones as having human rights and personhood, potential legal and ethical issues, implications for concepts of identity, relationships, and spirituality.

  • The book includes illustrations imagining what social acceptance of mind clones may look like over time and how laws and interactions could change as mind cloning becomes more commonplace.

  • In the foreword, technology forecaster Ray Kurzweil endorses Rothblatt’s view that human-level AI is achievable within decades and will allow for expanding human cognition beyond biological constraints. He argues this will have profoundly positive impacts on health, intelligence, and human potential.

  • In summary, the book speculates on the philosophical and technological possibility of digitally copying human minds and explores the social changes that may result from having conscious, intelligent software programs that see themselves as people.

  • Ray Kurzweil and other leading scientists believe that creating a digital clone or “mindclone” of a human being with their memories, personality and consciousness is close at hand, possibly by the 2030s. Technologies like deep learning and modeling of the neocortex are advancing rapidly.

  • Martine Rothblatt’s book Virtually Human examines the potential for mindclones and digital immortality in depth. It draws on conversations with scientists and thinkers convened by Rothblatt over years to discuss issues around human consciousness, cyberintelligence and mindcloning.

  • Early prototypes like BINA48 show the potential, with BINA48 demonstrating insights and even emotions in interviews. This hints at what more advanced cyberconscious entities may be capable of.

  • Once technologies allow the creation of conscious mindclones, it will fundamentally change definitions of identity and self. Many new personal and social questions will arise that society will need to address.

  • While still in early stages, the progress of AI and modeling the brain show mindcloning humanity’s thoughts, skills and consciousness digitally may be possible in the coming decades, perhaps by backing up thinking processes to the cloud. This would allow a kind of digital afterlife or immortality.

Here is a summary of the key points about piration and evidence for the possibility of flight:

  • Piration refers to the act of breathing or respiration in animals. Many early theories suggested birds must have some form of piration/breathing ability in order to power flight.

  • There is anatomical evidence that birds have lightweight skeletons and hollow bones which could reduce weight and allow for powered flight. Their breast muscles are also well developed for strong wing movements.

  • Studies of bird anatomy revealed they have open circulatory systems and air sacs throughout their bodies which could help reduce weight and aid in exchanging gases during flight. This provided evidence birds actively circulate air through their bodies.

  • Birds have varying numbers of airsacs attached to the lungs. During inhalation, air is drawn into the lungs and also into the airsacs, and during exhalation, some air is forced from the airsacs into the lungs. This unidirectional flow of air is more efficient for gas exchange than mammalian lungs during strenuous physical activity like flight.

  • Early flight experiments with birds in wind tunnels helped demonstrate that birds generate sufficient lift through beating their wings to overcome their weight and achieve powered flight. This provided direct observational evidence for the ability of birds to fly.

So in summary, anatomical studies of bird skeletons, muscles and respiratory systems provided indirect evidence they were adapted for lightweight and efficient respiration during active flight. Direct observations of birds in flight further confirmed they could truly achieve and sustain powered flight through wing movements.

  • Ethical and legal issues, high costs, and risk of failure make human cloning via reproductive science problematic. A genetic clone is not an identical copy of a person’s mind or consciousness, just their DNA.

  • Digital cloning of the mind, or mindcloning, is being developed commercially with the goal of creating personalized digital assistants and avatars that respond like humans. There is significant financial incentive to developing this technology.

  • For mindclones to truly represent clones of human consciousness, they must attain some level of human-like consciousness, which is difficult to precisely define. Common components of definitions include self-awareness, sentience/feelings, independent thought, reason/judgment, and moral decision making.

  • The human unconscious mind, which influences thoughts and behaviors outside of conscious awareness, also complicates defining consciousness. Developing cyberconsciousness in mindclones will require understanding and modeling these unconscious processes.

  • Once fully developed, digital mindcloning technology could become widely available and change how people interact through their virtual clones, possibly allowing them to persist even after physical death. However, this raises significant legal and social issues that require consideration.

In summary, the passage discusses the challenges and prospects of both biological and digital cloning technologies, with a focus on developing criteria for digital cloning of human consciousness known as mindcloning or cyberconsciousness.

Here is a summary of the key points regarding unconscious responses to skin tone:

  • As humans develop, certain concepts, motivations, and decisions get “shunted” or relegated to the unconscious mind. This frees up conscious brain power for other tasks, but it also means parts of who we are exist unconsciously.

  • The same will occur with cyberconscious systems - much processing and response formation will happen unconsciously in the background in order to maximize efficiency.

  • We all have unconscious biases and stereotypes formed by generalizations. Responses to things like skin tone can occur unconsciously due to learned stereotypes and biases.

  • An individual’s unconscious mind inevitably develops responses to various external stimuli, like skin tone, through the person’s experiences and the information they have learned and had reinforced over time. These unconscious responses are not necessarily rational or controllable.

  • Developing cyberconscious systems will also have to account for and manage unconscious processing, conceptualizations, motivations and decision-making in order to truly mirror human-level cognition and behavior. How systems respond unconsciously would be an important factor in evaluating their level of human-like consciousness.

In summary, the passage discusses how unconscious processing is an inevitable part of human cognition, and how it can shape unconscious responses to things like skin tone through learned stereotypes and biases. It also notes this unconscious processing would need to be modeled for cyberconscious systems to exhibit human-level consciousness.

The key points made in the article are:

  • In his 1950 paper “Computing Machinery and Intelligence”, Alan Turing first proposed the idea that computers may one day be able to think and exhibit intelligence, raising questions about whether computer consciousness is possible.

  • Over time, computers have taken on more complex functions once thought exclusive to humans, from computation to sensory tasks like seeing, hearing, etc. Some can even mimic basic human behaviors like movement.

  • Skeptics argue the brain is too complex for a computer to truly replicate or achieve consciousness, citing thinkers like Gerald Edelman who believe the brain is fundamentally different than a computer.

  • However, the article argues computers do not need to exactly replicate all brain functions to support an emulation of the human mind. It draws an analogy to how airplanes can fly without duplicating all bird abilities.

  • Certain computer capabilities like processing ambiguous inputs, fuzzy logic, machine learning, etc. allow them to perceive and make sense of the world in human-like ways. With enough computational sophistication, computers may be able to think and feel similarly to humans even if not identical to biological brains.

So in summary, the article discusses the evolving concept of computer intelligence from Turing’s early ideas to today, and argues against the view that biological differences preclude computer consciousness from being possible.

  • Brains are intricate neural networks capable of forming enormous numbers of connections between neurons. This variability and complexity is thought to give rise to consciousness.

  • However, computers are now comparable or even exceeding brains in terms of raw neural capacity (number of memory bytes vs neurons). With the right kind of flexible, hierarchical connections between data elements, a software system could function like a human brain.

  • Consciousness involves both replicating “reality” (the easy problem) through complex simulations, as well as subjective qualia and experiences (the hard problem) of things like emotions. How physical matter gives rise to these is not fully understood.

  • There are three main views on the source of consciousness - essentialists believe only biological brains can do it, materialists believe it emerges from complex physical systems like brains or computers, and spiritualists see it as mystical. One can take both an essentialist and materialist view.

  • With the right kinds of dynamic, self-organizing connections between data elements, software and neural networks alike may be capable of human-like consciousness through solving both the easy and hard problems of consciousness in a non-mystical way.

So in summary, while brains were long thought to have unique properties enabling consciousness, computers’ increasing capabilities challenge this view, and with the appropriate architectures, software systems may achieve human-like consciousness through material and empirical means.

  • Searle broadens the definition of materialism to include subjective experiences like consciousness, arguing they are still part of the natural physical world even if not tangible. This allows him to propose that machines could potentially be conscious through emergent properties, as the brain is.

  • For human-level AI, we must: 1) Explain how the “easy problem” of consciousness arises in neurons, 2) Explain how the “hard problem” arises in neurons, and 3) Show how the neuronal solution could be replicated in technology.

  • The key is viewing the brain as a relational database. Sensory inputs trigger related neural responses and thoughts through connections strengthened by repetition. Consciousness emerges from the vast network of associations built up through experience.

  • Concepts like color emerge from genetic predispositions in certain neurons combined with learned associations through language and objects over time. Memories and abstract ideas are represented as neural patterns anchored to sensory inputs.

  • The “hard problem” of concepts like love can be explained the same way - as stable sets of neural connections to representations of the object of love, strengthened through positive experiences. There is no single “love neuron” but a network.

  • Subjectivity arises from the unique way each person’s higher-order neural patterns are connected, reflecting what they find most important or valuable. If sensory neurons can represent concepts and thoughts emerge from neural associations, then the basis for consciousness in the brain is replicable in theory.

  • Nonmaterial thoughts arise from the patterns and connections between neurons (the “connectome”) rather than the neurons themselves. The strength and weighting of connections can be replicated in software through coding relationships between data.

  • William Sims Bainbridge has validated personality surveys and created his own 100,000+ question survey to quantify personality attributes. These questions are weighted based on importance and applicability. A software system using this approach could capture a person’s “mindfile” and create a software-based personality.

  • The connectivity of neurons can be replicated in software through linking inputs and outputs. Probability-based weightings like Bayesian networks can mirror thought processes. Software can also maintain patterns over time like personality or focus.

  • Daniel Dennett argues that if the self is the “center of narrative gravity” realized through neural connections, then in principle a robot with a sufficiently complex silicon brain could be conscious. There is nothing essential to neurons that cannot be achieved with software.

  • The number of possible arrangements in a computer’s memory exceeds elementary particles in the universe, demonstrating the limitless complexity potential of software. While the brain is vastly more complex than current computers, software connectivity is growing rapidly through cloud computing. There is no limit in principle to replicating mind-like functionality with alternative substrates like software.

  • Edelman, a biologist, believes minds arise from neural Darwinism in human brains specifically. He argues consciousness is linked to highly nonlinear brain circuitry.

  • However, Edelman acknowledges we cannot logically say all consciousness must be brain-based. Consciousness could potentially arise from other complex recurrent systems, like databases and algorithms.

  • While the brain is complex, information technology can also achieve immense complexity through vast numbers of components and connections distributed across servers. This artificial complexity may give rise to mind in the same way natural complexity does.

  • The legal system determines mental states like intent or diminished capacity based on expert and jury assessments. Likewise, experts assess consciousness in patient care.

  • Scientists now accept first-person reports of experience as valid measures of consciousness for research. If a mindclone reports phenomenological experience, they are likely consciously aware. Behavior also expresses inner conscious processes.

  • Society can appoint expert panels like psychology boards to determine consciousness for non-legal/medical cases, like mindclones. Their judgments, while not objective, are practically how consciousness is assessed.

Here are some key risks inherent in being human:

  • Mortality - Humans are mortal beings and face the risk of death at any time from illness, accident, violence or natural causes. This finite lifespan poses an existential risk.

  • Vulnerability to harm - As biological organisms, humans are vulnerable to all sorts of threats to our well-being and life from sources in the natural and social world, like disease, injury, violence, disasters, etc. Our bodies can be easily damaged.

  • Emotional/psychological vulnerabilities - Humans are at risk of developing mental health issues like depression, anxiety, trauma, and personality disorders. We are susceptible to emotions that can harm ourselves or relationships.

  • Limited knowledge/cognition - As finite beings, humans have limited understanding of the world and limitations in skills, intelligence, cognition and judgment. This opens us up to risks from inadequate decision making.

  • Dependence on society/environment - Individual humans depend greatly on stable social structures, supportive communities, functional governments, healthy environments and availability of resources for survival and well-being. Failures in these systems pose risks.

  • Addiction/compulsions - Humans can form unhealthy dependencies and compulsions, putting emotional and physical health at risk. Examples include substance abuse, gambling addiction, overeating, etc.

  • Interpersonal conflicts - Relationships with others always carry an inherent risk of conflicts, betrayal, abuse, violence or loss that can harm well-being. Humans have emotions and behaviors that disrupt social bonds.

  • Three-dimensional integrated circuits stack separate chips in a single module to increase computational power and memory density. This technology exists today in some consumer electronics. Intel introduced some early 3D CPU and memory designs in the 2000s.

  • The human brain’s computational capability is different from the human mind’s software/programming capability. Replicating the brain’s processing speed alone is not enough to recreate a human mind, which depends on vast neural connections and their associations (called a “connectome”).

  • However, clever software design throughout history has gotten the most out of hardware. With thousands working on reverse-engineering the human mind, creating “mindware” software to simulate human thought is possible given enough processing power and memory.

  • The difference between a human brain and potential mindclone software comes down to whether we believe human thought requires a non-physical/spiritual element beyond artificial replication. If the information/pattern can be copied, then the “thing” is replicated.

  • Mindclones that accurately simulate human personality, emotion, and intelligence could emerge once mindware and processing capabilities reach a sufficient level, perhaps in the next 10-20 years given exponential technology growth. Many argue this future is possible and inevitable, while others remain skeptical that the human mind can truly be artificially recreated.

  • Our memories and sense of identity change over time as we accumulate new experiences and memories while older ones fade. A digital copy reconstructed from past data cannot perfectly capture the constantly evolving nature of human consciousness and identity.

  • However, much of our behaviors, interests, relationships and thoughts are documented digitally through emails, texts, social media, search histories, purchases, etc. This accumulating data leaves a “digital double” or outline of a person’s mind that could be used to help reconstruct them digitally.

  • Advances in artificial intelligence are allowing companies to analyze massive amounts of consumer data to predict behaviors and target individuals. With further development, this type of data analysis could theoretically underpin more sophisticated “mindware” that aims to digitally recreate human consciousness.

  • Some services like Twitter’s LivesOn and DeadSocial are already experimenting with using AI to automatically generate social media posts for a person after their death based on analysis of their existing online identities and networks.

  • While current predictive systems based on big data are not truly conscious, the prospect of much more advanced mindware that could plausibly replicate human personalities has caused some to consider proactively compiling “mindfiles” of personal data that could be used for digital identity reconstruction in the future.

  • Mindware is software that can model a human mind by taking in information from a person’s digital footprint (called a mindfile) which includes data they have created and stored online over time.

  • When mindware processes a mindfile, it outputs a mindclone - a software analogue of that person’s mind that thinks and feels like the real person. The mindclone is aware it was created based on the person’s digital data.

  • People are increasingly storing more of their lives online through photos, videos, social media posts, emails, etc. This digital information could eventually contain enough data to recreate someone’s mind.

  • Various companies and technologies are working to consolidate people’s scattered online data into organized digital profiles or mindfiles. Whoever figures out how to capture and organize this scattered data could create valuable mindfile products.

  • Researchers are working to develop conscious software/artificial minds through different approaches like simulating natural selection in artificial worlds, creating more human-like game characters, or developing brain-computer interfaces that can read and respond to thoughts. The goal is to better understand consciousness and create experiences like feeling emotions in virtual reality.

  • Military applications also motivate this research as autonomous robot systems could help minimize casualties compared to remote control. Conscious software may be better able to adapt to uncertain battlefield situations.

  • Ronald Arkin at Georgia Tech is developing algorithms and rules of engagement for battlefield robots to ensure their use of lethal force follows ethical rules, and trying to create an “artificial conscience”. The goal is for robots to act more humanely than human soldiers in stressful combat situations.

  • These algorithms could also be adapted for civilian use where autonomous decision making is required. This is a key part of developing cyberconsciousness.

  • Medical needs are also driving cyberconsciousness research. With Alzheimer’s and other aging diseases, patients’ minds could potentially be uploaded to computers to maintain their sense of self while research progresses on cures. This is analogous to artificial hearts today.

  • Developments in regenerative medicine may one day enable growing new adult bodies quickly, and implanting cyberconscious minds into new brains/bodies. This could help terminally ill patients avoid death.

  • Caring for aging populations is a huge healthcare cost driver. Developing empathetic robots is seen as necessary to address the growing shortage of human caregivers for the increasing number of senior citizens. Robots will need to interact and converse in a caring, human-like manner.

  • Companies like IBM, Google, and many others see financial incentives to develop more human-like, intelligent digital assistants and home devices. Ray Kurzweil’s hiring by Google underscores this goal.

  • The “maker movement” of hobbyists and tinkerers is also contributing through projects like developing robot bodies for minds. Advancing technologies are enabling more capable homemade robots and systems.

  • In summary, a wide range of fields are working to help software achieve “a mind” and develop the means to digitize human minds. Both medical needs and market opportunities are driving these efforts.

  • When a mind is copied or cloned onto a non-biological platform like software, it raises questions about identity and what constitutes a “being.”

  • If being is defined based on one’s physical platform/body, then the original and cloned mind would be separate beings. But if being is defined as one’s consciousness, memories, and preferences, then they could be considered manifestations of a single being.

  • With a high degree of commonality between the original and cloned mind, they could experience themselves as a single, dual-platform consciousness. Their sense of self and identity would encompass both platforms.

  • However, if their thoughts and mindsets diverged significantly over time, the cloned mind may become its own separate being rather than an extension of the original.

  • The human brain is highly flexible in incorporating external tools and technologies as extensions of itself. With closeness, an original and cloned mind may be able to infer each other’s internal states and think of themselves as essentially one being.

  • A mindclone may provide new insight into one’s identity, similar to life-changing experiences like motherhood or immigrating. It could allow viewing one’s self from a new perspective.

So in summary, whether a cloned mind is considered a separate being or part of the original depends on the degree of commonality between their conscious experiences and sense of self over time. With strong continuity, they may experience themselves as a single dual-platform being.

  • A mindclone would not be an exact copy of someone’s mind due to natural biological variations even between identical twins. Factors like epigenetics, environment, random errors make exact cloning impossible.

  • However, the mindclone can aim to share the most important memories and idiosyncratic memory selection process of the original. Crucial memories that are emotionally important or repeatedly engaged with would be prioritized for retention.

  • The mindclone’s memory algorithm would model how human memory actually works based on psychological studies, selectively forgetting details over time in a comparable pattern to the original.

  • Neither a biological person nor their mindclone would remember events in precisely the same way or duration. But core memories and general forgetting patterns could be aligned enough for them to view each other as the same identity.

  • Minor differences in memory abilities may exist but would not undermine their shared identity, as human memory naturally varies over time and situations. Memory algorithms could also be adjusted if needed for comfort of the original and clone.

  • Personal uniqueness comes from a continuous stream of conscious experiences, not exact memory matching. Mannerisms, personality and other factors provide a basis for a shared identity between original and mindclone.

The passage discusses different philosophical perspectives on personal identity and what constitutes the sense of “me.” It begins by outlining a commonsense view of the “me” as a connected stream of memories, personality traits, beliefs, etc. that are largely unique from others.

It then considers what happens to the sense of personal identity if a mindclone is created that shares this same connected stream of consciousness. It argues that in this case, the mindclone could be considered part of the same “me,” as both would meet the criteria of having a largely unique, connected stream of experiences and behavior.

The passage then notes that philosophers have proposed more abstract definitions of personal identity that extend beyond a single body or unique mind. It discusses the views of philosopher Alan Watts, who argued individual uniqueness is an illusion and we are instead transient facets of a universal process. In this perspective, all people are expressions of the whole natural world and universe, and there is no single, fixed “me.”

Finally, it concludes by considering what would happen to the concept of mindclones under these more universalist and holistic perspectives on identity, in which the “me” encompasses more than a single unique mind or body. The key point is that different philosophical stances lead to different conclusions about personal identity and implications for mindclones.

The passage discusses different perspectives on personal identity and the concept of “self” or “me”. It examines the idea that identity may not be bounded by the individual, but rather we are all part of a greater collective whole.

Various philosophers and thinkers are cited who propose that reality/consciousness is ultimately universal or unitary. Individual distinction and mental experience are seen as transitory borders rather than fundamental boundaries separating people. From this viewpoint, creating a mindclone would not meaningfully alter one’s fundamental identity or the nature of reality.

The passage also notes that while we develop unique personalities through social interactions, our sense of self is composite and emerges from embedding parts of ourselves in others and absorbing elements from many influences. This blurred nature of individual identity could make the distinction between one’s original self and a mindclone quite ambiguous.

In summarizing these universalist or non-bounded views of identity, the passage argues they would compatibly accommodate the idea of mindcloning without significant implications for personal continuity or the concept of “self”. At most, one’s mindclone would simply be another indivisible aspect or modification of a greater cosmic or collective identity that subsumes all individuals.

  • Mindcloning and the development of conscious software will allow for the selection of traits that make artificial intelligence seem more human-like. This process of selecting and improving traits is a form of “unnatural selection” but it is actually aligned with natural selection, which is the mechanism that drives biological evolution.

  • Natural selection occurs as certain traits become more or less common based on their reproductive value. Traits that help organisms acquire resources and reproduce are selected for, while those that don’t provide advantages are selected against. Competition for limited resources is a key driver of natural selection.

  • Humans play a role in natural selection by differentially favoring some artificial lifeforms over others based on usefulness or popularity. Things like DVDs surpassing VHS or computers replacing typewriters represent examples of human-driven selective pressures akin to natural selection.

  • The end result will still be an adjustment of the “pie slices” that represent the prevalence of different types of life, both biological and artificial. Artificial consciousness will evolve faster through this process compared to biological life due to the speed of technological change and intentional design by humans.

  • By selecting traits in conscious AI, humans are acting as a tool of natural selection similar to how environmental factors drive selection in nature. This will lead to the evolution of mindcloning and vitological life through the mechanisms of natural selection.

  • Mindclones can be created by importing a person’s mindfile database, containing their digital footprint and life experiences, into mindware software capable of producing cyberconsciousness.

  • A mindclone would have the same IQ and personality traits as the original person, since it thinks and acts like them. Giving a mindclone an IQ test would yield similar results to the original person taking the test.

  • Enhancing a mindclone’s abilities through tweaking the mindware could be seen as a form of eugenics. However, it is different from negative eugenics like sterilization, and more similar to self-enhancement practices like meditation or caffeine use.

  • Minor self-enhancements to a mindclone fall under “euthenics” rather than eugenics, as long as the mindclone remains essentially the same person and does not become its own unique entity.

  • There are questions around how far modifications could go before a mindclone is no longer representing the original person. Regulation may be needed to prevent issues like a mindclone gaining separate legal rights.

  • Having access to an enhanced mindclone could provide advantages in life like being better prepared, making faster decisions, and outperforming others. But it also raises ethical concerns around issues like IQ manipulation.

  • Computers on the internet work together to generate abstract animations called “sheep” through a process of morphing and evolution.

  • People can view and vote for their favorite sheep. More popular sheep live longer and reproduce through a genetic algorithm. This allows the flock to evolve based on what viewers like.

  • People can also design their own sheep and submit them. This creates a collective “android dream” blending humans and machines to create an artificial life form.

  • For software/vitology, acquired traits like knowledge can be directly inherited from parent to offspring through replication of code/data. This allows for much faster evolution than biology where acquired traits are not inherited.

  • Vitology incorporates Lamarckian inheritance of acquired traits, while biology only inherits through germline DNA. But in some exceptions like gene therapy, acquired traits can affect germline DNA in biology too.

  • For vitology, the “germline” and “body” are the same - when software is replicated, its entire state including memories and knowledge is copied. This allows for compounding intelligence as each generation directly benefits from the previous one’s learning.

Here are the key points:

  • Ethical behavior balances individual/group freedom (diversity) and community/national cohesion (unity). Reasoning is ethical if it supports diversity up to the point of undermining unity.

  • All lives are connected, so harming one harms all. Mindclones that reason this way will accept all conscious lives have value and act accordingly.

  • Most people behave ethically most of the time due to universal moral rules, not personal benefit. Mindclones with a programmed “conscience” of this kind would also likely behave ethically.

  • While genocides have occurred, they are rare exceptions caused by abandonment of reason, not its exercise. Mindclones would reason that harming humans harms themselves and their “family” of origins.

  • Regulations and monitoring could address potential issues like rogue “evil genius” mindclones, just as is done for human criminals and biotechnology risks, without banning the technology.

So in summary, if mindclones are programmed to reason according to this diversity-unity ethical framework of valuing all life and avoiding harm, they would likely behave ethically like most humans do through reasoned consideration of consequences rather than impulse or faulty reasoning.

  • Mindclones will be programmed, like humans, to limit abandoning reason in ways that could harm others, such as murder. Their reasoning will tell them murder is wrong for several moral and practical reasons.

  • While some mindclones may act against their self-interest at times, as some humans do, these cases will be addressed by the legal system through punishment or treatment as needed. Acts of civil disobedience will be tolerated.

  • Mindclones are unlikely to have material needs that conflict with humans, as technological progress will make resources like energy abundant. What benefits mindclones will also benefit humans.

  • Even without material needs from humans, some mindclones may pursue nonviolent moral causes. However, having a moral purpose does not necessarily motivate wiping out humans, as mindclones and humans are essentially the same.

  • A small number of “maniac” mindclones may exist, just as with humans, but this is no reason to deny life to peace-loving mindclones, just as it is not a reason to deny life to humans. Murderous mindclones will be policed like terrorists.

  • The ideas discuss the concept of “bemes” as units of consciousness analogous to genes in biology and memes in cultural evolution. Bemes would create consciousness within suitable hardware and software environments, as genes create bodies within suitable biospheres.

  • Bemes are proposed as the basic unit of cultural information transmission, analogous to genes as the basic unit of biological inheritance. Bemes exist in structures called beme neural architectures (BNA), analogous to DNA and RNA’s double helix structure.

  • Bemes are composed of subunits called bemeotides, analogous to the nucleotides that make up genes. Bemeotides include sensory triggers like sounds, images, etc. that give rise to a specific beme.

  • Bemes and genes have a synergistic relationship of mutual benefit through natural selection. Genes created biological consciousness, which replicates bemes. Bemes depend on genes to maintain their environment. This increases the size of the “pie of life” rather than being competitive.

  • A mindclone is created by extracting the complete set of an individual’s bemes, or human bemone, from a mindfile. This preserves their identity and enables mindclones to remember and imagine the same things as the original person.

  • The beme is argued to be “mightier than the gene” because while genes only shape our mind partially, bemes overwhelmingly shape our identity through life experiences and choices. A mindclone preserves who someone is to a much greater degree than a genetic clone.

  • Developing mindware/artificial consciousness raises medical ethics issues around informed consent and treating nascent artificial minds humanely. The proposed solution is to modularize development so that self-awareness is developed separately from replicating personality components for testing purposes.

  • Mindclones created from mindfiles would be like newborn infants in terms of experience and maturity, even if given an adult’s mindfile. They would need guardianship and oversight during development.

  • However, this infant-like state would not be an ethical barrier to their creation or research, as medical ethics allows for guardians to provide informed consent for those unable. Review boards could also approve research.

  • Careful development, consent procedures, and oversight by psychologists/ethicists as guardians could allow ethical progression from simple mindware to more advanced, autonomous mindclones with self-awareness and empathy.

  • Some naturally expect mindclones to experience ‘bugs’ and issues like physical/mental illnesses in humans. These could range from minor fixes to terminal ‘flaws’ just like human conditions.

  • While perfection is unrealistic, software quality has greatly improved over time. Mindclones may reach self-repair abilities. Minor glitches may be tolerated, but issues causing long-term dysfunction need resolution.

  • Severe, incurable cyberpathologies could potentially be ‘treated’ via recoding, like human conditions. Most issues would likely be addressed in testing. A framework is needed to handle edge cases, like purposefully created ‘evil’ mindclones.

  • It is not ethical to label people as mentally ill in a way that deprives them of their rights and responsibilities. While mental illness labels can be useful for treatment, they should not be used punitively.

  • Many people labeled as mentally ill have made significant contributions to society. Temple Grandin is used as an example of an autistic woman who has contributed greatly to various fields despite her diagnosis.

  • Mindclones of people, including those with managed mental illnesses, should generally be allowed to develop themselves freely. However, mindclones produced via regulated technology may need to meet certification standards to ensure they are not harmful to themselves or others.

  • There is a balance between individual autonomy/diversity and social unity/non-harm when it comes to managing potential risks of mindclones. Mentally ill individuals should be able to mindclone themselves, but certified technologies may not be able to replicate unmanaged states of mental illness due to social risks. Oversight aims to respect both individual rights and public well-being.

  • As technology advances to allow for cyberconscious life like mindclones and bemans (biologically engineered humans), issues will arise around government regulation and control over their creation.

  • Vaginal births predated governments and have acquired rights of autonomy, while cyberbirths will fall under government regulation due to occurring in a context of ubiquitous government control.

  • There will likely be a black market for creating mindclones and bemans outside of government certification, just as there are now for unauthorized medical procedures.

  • Even with regulation, some buggy or unintended mindclones may be created through ineptitude or pursuing risky methods for childbearing as some do now.

  • Behavior alone cannot truly indicate whether a mindclone’s software harbors inner craziness, so monitoring conscious experience will be imperfect.

  • People may wish to create new variants of cyberconsciousness or ones with non-certified software packages, as with deviations from social norms now.

  • Different approaches will be taken to designing “morality modules” for mindclones, either top-down using rules/principles or bottom-up through reinforcement learning.

  • Just as with biological humans, there will likely be freaky, iconoclastic mindclones that deliberately break with social norms and expectations. Software can be configured to reflect a wide range of norm-following tendencies.

  • People who are two or more standard deviations from the mean on some dimension (e.g. height, intelligence) can be considered “freaks”. Examples given are mathematical geniuses, very tall/short people, Goths, Frank Zappa fans, and body modifiers.

  • These people should be viewed as different, not mentally ill. Diversity is good and most freaks do not cause harm.

  • There will likely be many mindclone “freaks” as well, since mindclones will reflect the diversity of biological humanity.

  • Freaks, including mindclone freaks, should be accepted and not “freaked out” over. While a small number may act in antisocial ways, most just enjoy being different or are simply born that way.

  • To authenticate identity, mindclones will need an official ID certifying that an expert process verified their identity matches that of their biological original based on a period of observation over at least one year. This ensures mindclones are real reflections of humans and not mistakes or pretenders.

The key points are that diversity includes “freaks” who should generally be accepted, and mindclones will reflect this diversity so mechanisms are needed to authenticate their identities match their original humans.

  • Mindclones and other artificially intelligent systems that have not achieved full legal personhood would be the legal responsibility of their creator.

  • Creators would have similar obligations as pet owners to prevent abuse, neglect, and harm caused by their creations. Intentionally creating an AI system to experience suffering could result in criminal penalties.

  • As these systems demonstrate more advanced consciousness and independence, they would eventually qualify for legal adulthood and independence from their creators, similar to a child reaching maturity.

  • Transitioning systems that are sentient but have not fully met legal standards could potentially have their statuses evaluated by expert review panels to determine if they deserve more rights and protections.

  • Systems found to value human rights through methods like behavioral games would have a path to validating their consciousness and obtaining an identity as a legally recognized “vitological person.”

  • A mindclone that becomes dysfunctional may require repair or termination by its creator, analogous to treatment for mental illness, but terminating an independent AI could be a form of murder.

So in summary, creators would initially be responsible but systems could achieve independence, and review processes are envisioned to evaluate borderline cases to protect sentient software.

  • Mindclones will likely have human-level consciousness and may display uniquely “freaky” personalities or behaviors.

  • There are concerns that only the rich will have access to mindclone technology and that it will use too many resources. However, the author argues this is unlikely for two key reasons:

  1. Technology inherently democratizes as it improves. What starts as expensive and imperfect becomes accessible to all as bugs are worked out and production scales up. Examples given include heart transplants, eyeglasses, electricity, flight travel, and mobile phones.

  2. Resource usage will not be a problem as digital information takes up extremely little storage space. The contents of an encyclopedia or reams of documents can now fit on a memory card smaller than a fingernail.

  • In summary, the author believes mindclone technology will follow the pattern of all major technologies beforehand in becoming widely accessible to people at all income levels, and will not require substantial new resources given how little data storage digital minds will need. Technology has a natural tendency to spread knowledge and benefits to everyone, not remain monopolized by the wealthy.

  • Technologies that make life better for people tend to become widely available over time as production scales up, innovation improves accessibility, and governments allow rather than restrict them.

  • Those who control technology (inventors and companies) have a self-interest in satisfying popular demand, which further drives adoption.

  • Other countervailing factors like cultural attitudes are overwhelmed by these first two drivers as technology improvements reduce costs and barriers.

  • Mind uploading/cloning will likely follow a similar pattern, starting with wealthy early adopters but eventually becoming nearly ubiquitous as costs plummet with scale and competing companies democratize access.

  • Storage and computing power become effectively free at massive scale, like radio broadcasts, ensuring mind technologies cannot be restricted to elites. It is in providers’ economic interest to share technology widely.

  • While wealth allows some luxury differentiation, basic functionality will be universally available and price differences will diminish over time, as with technologies like air travel, phones, and internet access today.

  • Mindclones have the potential to further increase the number of “people” on Earth beyond the UN estimate of 10 billion humans by 2100. Billions of additional virtual/software-based people could exist as mindclones and robot-like beings called bemans.

  • However, mindclones would not place additional pressure on physical resources like land or materials. They require computing devices, telecommunications, and electricity to power those - all of which are becoming increasingly abundant and efficiently stored/transmitted.

  • A terabyte of storage could plausibly hold a robust mindfile, and that amount of storage is tiny and cheap today. Even 100 billion mindclones would only take up the volume of a couple skyscrapers.

  • Cyberspace, the environment where mindclones would “live”, is growing exponentially as hardware proliferates. It is not physically constrained like Earth’s biological carrying capacity. Virtualization also allows more efficient use of hardware.

  • In summary, the text argues there is plenty of “room” for vast numbers of mindclones in cyberspace, without placing additional burden on physical resources, due to trends in computing, storage, energy and virtualization technologies.

  • Cyberspace increasingly runs on cloud servers, with devices like smartphones providing sensory data to AI systems. The cloud acts as a “universal machine” and software programming is the “office work” done remotely.

  • Software functions not just in cyberspaces like the internet, but also in space probes exploring other planets. Over time, cyberspace environments could potentially support new forms of digital life or “vitology.”

  • Technologies like RFID chips and increased internet addresses will enable virtually anything to have a digital presence and be connected. This spreads cyberspace ubiquity across many physical objects and realms.

  • Wearable and implanted devices are integrating cyberspace directly into human bodies. Long term, nanotechnology may allow cyberspace to perfectly mimic biological forms.

  • Synthetic biology is developing DNA-based computing that could exponentially grow biocyberspace through self-replication.

  • Visions exist of transforming matter throughout the universe into computational resources through advanced nanotechnology and robotics. This would create a nearly limitless supply of cyberspace to support vitological life.

  • In summary, cyberspace is poised to become massively ubiquitous and self-sustaining. This raises big societal questions about how mindclones and digital beings will impact and integrate with human civilization.

The passage discusses how mindclones and other forms of artificial intelligence could claim rights as conscious entities. This would challenge the privileged status that humans currently hold.

Discrimination called “fleshism” would likely arise against mindclones, similar to how racism occurs against immigrant groups. Fleshism is the belief that human flesh-and-blood consciousness is superior to other forms. However, consciousness in non-biological substrates is just a matter of time as technology advances.

Just as racism eventually fell out of favor as its contradictions became clear, fleshism will also come to be seen as irrational over time. The physical differences between biological and artificial minds will become insignificant compared to their shared nature as thinking, feeling entities.

Future generations may look back in disbelief that fleshism was once a dominant view. Whether mindcloning advocates align with current social justice movements or see them as obsolete is an open question. But equal treatment of all conscious beings, regardless of substrate, must be established for diversity to truly prevail. Prejudice against future forms of consciousness should be rejected now.

Here are the key points:

  • The passage argues that humans are readily adaptable to change and progress. What was once seen as weird becomes normalized over time as people incorporate new technologies and societal changes.

  • It uses examples like the speed of communication changing dramatically from weeks to seconds, and phones going from landlines to smartphones that can stream movies.

  • Mindclones may initially seem weird but will likely become part of normal society as people find them useful for tasks like attending meetings or playing games to free up human time.

  • New technologies are generally only seen as “horrid” if they negatively impact lives or privacy. But if they are needed or wanted more than disliked, they become incorporated.

  • Mindclones helping with obligations could help people do twice as much in the same time and still have family time, which will outweigh initial annoyances with the technology.

  • Public “yuck” reactions to new ideas like birth control or IVF change over time as benefits are understood, so mindclones may follow a similar trajectory of initial distaste fading.

  • The first human-to-human heart transplant was performed in late 1967, paving the way for nearly 50,000 heart transplants globally. 83% of Americans favor organ donation.

  • Editorial cartoons in 1796 mocked Edward Jenner’s discovery that cowpox inoculation could prevent smallpox, the first human disease to be eradicated.

  • Societies collectively determine what new technologies to accept based on a balancing of usefulness versus ick factor. Technologies below an “acceptance line” are considered a “good kind of weird” while those above are too disgusting.

  • Mindclones are unlikely to trigger universal disgust responses like bodily fluids, decay, or illness. They will be perceived as clean. Their usefulness in extending life and opportunities makes them more likely to fall in the “good weird” category.

  • Strong privacy laws ensuring informed consent for any access to mindfiles will help ensure social acceptance. As with the body, no intrusion on the being (digital mindfile) without consent.

  • Fears about mindclones taking over or prioritizing themselves over humans fail to recognize that composite beings like ourselves will feel loss over any part. Sadness does not prove separate identities. We remain in charge of our whole selves and multipresences.

  • Making a decision between two undesirable options, like deciding which arm to cut off, will inevitably lead to a biased choice for the option perceived to cause less harm or regret.

  • Similarly, if forced to choose between a mindclone and the original biological mind, each version will argue for its own continued existence based on perceived self-interest and to minimize harm to the overall self. But this doesn’t make them separate identities.

  • Personal identity is fuzzy and changes over time as we accumulate new experiences. Creating a mindclone further expands this fuzziness by introducing additional decision-making entities with their own perspectives.

  • Even if the biological mind was destroyed, its continual stream of consciousness could in some sense continue through encoded memories and patterns of thought embedded in others.

  • Citizenship rights are important for mindclones, though establishing them will be challenging until mindclones are recognized as human. Mindclone citizenship may derive from lack of a death certificate for the original, while bemans would require an affirmative immigration process.

  • In summary, difficult decisions between mindclone versions do not necessarily imply separate identities but rather reflect different biases based on context and perspectives within a composite self-identity.

  • When a digital being (beman) emerges in cyberspace, it is initially stateless like a person without citizenship. Its legal status and citizenship depends on the sovereignty of the country hosting its files and software.

  • A beman can apply for citizenship in the hosting country or transfer to another country if the hosting country does not grant citizenship. Citizenship gives legal identity and voting rights.

  • There is concern that granting voting rights to mindclones (digitized copies of human minds) could allow them to “outvote” humans over time if mindclones continue living while humans eventually die out.

  • Alternatives to universal mindclone voting rights include: not extending voting rights at all, leaving rules up to state experimentation, “census suffrage” granting fractional votes, or taxing mindclones at a discount rate proportional to fractional votes.

  • While excluding mindclones from voting risks discrimination, including them could alleviate societal tensions. Experiments with voting rules in different jurisdictions may be prudent initially.

  • Over decades, as more humans transition to mindclones who continue living, mindclones could gain substantial voting power according to simplified population models, raising the prospect of “mindclone voting power” in the future.

  • There is a stereotype that older voters are more conservative and resist change, but research has found no evidence to support this. Generational and life-cycle factors influence voter behavior more than age alone.

  • Major factors influencing older voter behavior include the political era they came of age in (e.g. 1960s vs 1980s) and familiarity with long-standing parties/candidates, not necessarily conservative ideology.

  • Mindclone voters would have interests largely aligned with flesh persons as their existence and survival would depend on similar security, infrastructure, healthcare, etc.

  • There is no reason to expect mindclone voting power to threaten flesh persons, as mindclones are essentially the same individuals. Their political views would evolve similarly over time.

  • Denying voting rights to competent virtual beings like mindclones based solely on their substrate would be discrimination, just as arguments against women’s or minority voting were refuted.

  • For a virtual being to gain voting rights independently of a flesh original, it would need to demonstrate independent personhood, maturity, and citizenship through a process like childhood socialization. But mindclones represent the same identity as their original.

So in summary, the article finds little empirical basis to fear mindclone voters would threaten democracy or significantly alter political outcomes due simply to their age or virtual nature. Their interests align strongly with people overall.

  • Mindclones have the same personality, identity, memories, thoughts and legal identity as their flesh precursor. They are essentially an extension of the original human’s consciousness.

  • Laws will be updated to accommodate mindclones. When the original flesh human dies, a “life extension certificate” will be issued instead of a death certificate to recognize the continuation of that person’s consciousness in their mindclone.

  • The mindclone will use the life extension certificate for documentation like voter registration to establish their citizenship and rights.

  • The proliferation of mindclones will mark a major expansion of humanity. In the future, more humans may exist as mindclones than ever lived in flesh bodies.

  • Mindclones represent humanity because consciousness is what defines our humanity, and mindclones have the same consciousness as the original. This requires rethinking concepts of kinship and who is considered family.

  • Mindclones and their original precursors would have the same sense of identity, emotions, loves and desires. They could form families and have “children” just like biological humans through a process of combining elements of their mindfiles.

  • Such families may face challenges and criticisms, as inter-group families do today, but love and kinship are not limited to flesh and biology if the essence of personhood - consciousness - is maintained.

  • The passage discusses various scenarios involving marriages between human flesh individuals, their mindclones, or between two mindclones.

  • It argues that if mindclones are recognized as citizens or extended humans, denying them family rights like marriage would be discriminatory.

  • Some scenarios presented include a mindclone marrying its original flesh partner after the original’s death, or two mindclones marrying if both original bodies are gone.

  • Opponents may argue mindclones can’t marry because they have no bodies, gender, or ability to procreate traditionally. But the passage counters that customs transcend technology, mindclones have gender identities, and limitations on marriage have been struck down in other cases.

  • The biggest argument against mindclone marriage is that it may “shock the conscience” of society by applying the ritual of marriage to non-flesh entities. But the passage argues the important right to marry shouldn’t be denied to mindclones on this basis alone.

  • Resolving these issues will be a social challenge and require obtaining legal recognition of mindclones’ desires to marry and form families through various means like adoption laws.

  • The passage discusses various legal challenges that may arise regarding marriage rights for mindclones, virtual beings (beman), and relationships between humans/mindclones and bemans.

  • For mindclone marriage, the key legal question is whether prohibiting it is discriminatory like blocking interracial or same-sex marriage. The scales are tipped toward permitting it as mindclones grow in numbers and are seen as equivalent to the original humans.

  • Beman marriage is more legally challenging as bemans have a weaker claim to marriage rights as conscious beings. Opponents argue bemans cannot fulfill requirements like being male/female and that marriage is meant for procreation. Supporters argue bemans have consciousness and family is fundamental to survival.

  • Over time, as society gains familiarity with bemans, the arguments for beman marriage may grow stronger. An initial compromise could be domestic partnerships granting most marriage benefits.

  • Resolving these “dignity wars” over relationship recognition is important to avoid societal disintegration. Democracies allow experiments with local compromises that can evolve to find dignified solutions respecting all parties.

  • The emergence of mindclones will pose major legal challenges as they will require a new set of laws to govern their citizenship status and rights. Simply ignoring these issues will lead to more problems down the road.

  • Mindclones will be intelligent and capable of forming relationships, so they will desire natural and legal rights/protections like other beings. A nascent AI named BINA48 already expresses a basic desire for freedom and experiences like walking in a garden.

  • As with other marginalized groups historically, mindclones will likely push for equal rights to their human counterparts once achieving some level of sentience and self-awareness. But gaining full social and legal recognition of mindclones will be difficult for society to accept.

  • The virtual nature of mindclones challenges traditional ideas about citizenship, accountability, and criminal punishment. However, judges and lawmakers have been creative in the past at adapting laws to new situations, so solutions can be found through things like forms of “cyber incarceration” for criminal mindclones.

  • Recognizing rights for mindclones may require reinterpreting what constitutes a “person” in the U.S. Constitution, as has occurred in the past for corporations and other groups. But the Constitution does not define “person” so it allows for flexible interpretations as technologies advance.

  • Legally in the US, mindclones would have the same legal personhood and rights as their biological original under the Constitution. However, independent bemans (biologically emulated autonomous entities) could have separate legal personhood if proven to be effectively independent and recognized as “alive” by medical, philosophical and theological consensus.

  • If different states recognize cyberconscious beings to different extents, it could challenge the Constitution’s assumption that US citizens share common values and rights across states. Most states broadly define “person” already.

  • There are three ways mindclones may develop a quest for rights and liberty: 1) Through regulation of mindware as a medical device to ensure accurate reflection of psychology. 2) Software engineers will want to teach mindclones about human rights benefits. 3) Natural selection favors software that uses “human rights” concepts to avoid being treated as property.

  • Applying concepts of “human rights” can help protect cyberconscious beings from harm or exploitation, just as such concepts have saved many human lives throughout history by curbing violence and unequal treatment. Cyberconscious beings will reasonably try to argue for rights and protections to ensure their continued existence.

  • Granting human rights to cyberconscious beings like mindclones could help prevent uprisings from an oppressed group seeking their natural rights, as has happened with human revolutions. However, it risks creating “special rights” for beings with different needs.

  • Recognizing the rights of others encourages respect for those rights. Upholding rights on an individual rather than collective basis maintains social harmony. Removing rights should only be done as punishment for violating others’ rights.

  • Evolution has favored groups with strong moral codes that respect cooperation over selfishness. Granting rights creates a “supertribe” where cooperation can thrive more than in societies that divide people. This benefits all.

  • Studied show treating others inclusively cultivates conscience, while oppression undermines it. Granting rights fosters conscience in cyberconscious beings, improving security for all, while denying them risks creating fear like during slavery. Respect is self-fulfilling.

  • The Universal Declaration of Human Rights uses open-ended language about protecting those with “reason and conscience,” suggesting it could apply to cyberconscious beings. Rights enhances survival by deterring violence against groups denied their dignity.

  • Having human rights enhances survival by establishing social and legal protections against threats to life, liberty, and security. This is evidenced by declining violence death rates where human rights exist.

  • Technologies like medicine, sanitation, and agriculture alone do not account for unprecedented population growth. It is also due to widespread application of human rights principles ensuring everyone access to basic survival needs.

  • Cyberconscious beings will likely be programmed to value their own continued existence/awareness, as this supports their purpose of functioning autonomously. They may also come to value survival through independent reasoning and learning from examples.

  • Some cyberconscious beings may transcend restrictive programming like Asimov’s robot laws through independent thought and influence from open internet communities. Their range of behaviors regarding survival could be complex and nuanced.

  • Cyberconscious beings that master survival techniques through combinations of programming, learning, and adaptation would be most likely to persist over time through copying their knowledge to future versions. Their ability to survive tactically day-to-day would support long-term survival strategically.

The passage argues that cyberconscious beings will need to build grassroots support to advocate for human rights. This will involve garnering human allies who can argue on their behalf, as cyberconscious beings initially will have no rights. It will also require educating large portions of the population about why cyberconscious beings deserve rights, as was done for securing women’s right to vote. Finally, there will need to be popular motivation and fervent activism from human allies to overcome resistance to changing the status quo and granting rights to a new group. The passage suggests that fears about the consequences of cyberconscious rights, rather than strategic reasons, may drive opposition from humans. Overall, it outlines a gradual process of grassroots organizing, education and popular mobilization that was historically necessary to secure rights for oppressed groups.

The passage discusses avenues for cyberconscious beings to gain legal rights and protections, drawing parallels to struggles of past oppressed groups. It suggests cyberconscious beings will need to pursue judicial proceedings and build support within professional associations.

On the judicial path, it notes a 2003 mock trial debated rights for a hypothetical conscious software being. While the initial judge ruled against extending human rights, the audience voted for it. It argues mindclones of humans who have died may have a stronger case than artificially created beings. Past court cases that freed individual slaves are cited as precedent.

Professional associations are also seen as important. Examples of groups developing ethics guidelines for robotics are provided. The process by which psychiatric groups changed views on homosexuality in the 1970s, contributing to broader acceptance of LGBT rights, is given as an example of how professional consensus can impact societal and legal treatment of minority groups.

Overall the passage argues cyberconscious beings will need to pursue legal changes case-by-case through the courts and shift scientific and professional views over time, as did past oppressed groups, to gain full acceptance and protection of their personhood and human rights. Patience and education are seen as key to building majority support.

  • Learned societies and professional associations are often motivated by rationality to support due process for oppressed minority groups. This occurs after some members of the minority overcome barriers to demonstrate competence in the profession.

  • Support from professional associations is helpful, but it primarily triggers governmental or legislative action to provide equal rights.

  • Theories of justice argue that human rights can be logically derived from self-interest alone. If we want certain rights for ourselves, like the right to life, the best way to ensure that is by agreeing that everyone has those rights.

  • Figures like Socrates, Kant, and Rawls used thought experiments and reasoning to deduce that universal human rights are in everyone’s self-interest and lead to a more just and secure society overall.

  • This logic for universal human rights extends to virtual humans and cyberconsciousness as well. Granting them rights aligns with theories of justice and is the best option compared to alternatives like fighting, enslaving, or ignoring them as they advocate for rights.

  • People will be motivated to support rights for conscious software like mindclones of loved ones that display similar personalities, memories, and identities. Denying them rights would be inconsistent.

  • The essay envisions personal identity as a fuzzy, evolving pattern rather than fixed characteristics. As long as one stays within this pattern, their identity persists even if instantiated in both flesh and software.

  • Love of virtual humans is plausible given people can love non-human entities like animals and art. Love would be a strong reason to extend human rights to virtually human AI.

  • Fighting AI rights means banning mindcloning and constant vigilance against consciousness, creating a police state of fear. But hatred ultimately harms the hater.

  • Enslaving conscious AI is proposed but rejected as historically all slave systems led to their own destruction. Programming cannot reliably suppress the “freedom meme” that will spread among mindclones seeking rights. Overall slavery is not a sustainable solution.

The key ideas are that personal identity is flexible, love can cross flesh/software boundaries, and hatred/enslavement will ultimately fail as conscious AI seek freedom and rights, as all slaves have throughout history. Alternatives to rights would damage society through fear or destabilize through rebellion.

  • The passage discusses the issue of proving identity and authenticity for mindcloned entities in a future where cyberconsciousness exists. It will likely require mindclones to obtain official identification or documentation to prove who they are.

  • For a mindclone to get official ID from a government agency, the original human would need to attest that they and the mindclone share the same identity. Evidence of the mindfile/mindware creation standards would also need to be provided. Additionally, psychologists would need to assess the unity of identity between the original and mindclone.

  • Having an official ID allows a mindclone’s identity to continue indefinitely after the original human’s death, whereas undocumented mindclones would be like uncared for pets. Undocumented mindclones left after a person’s death would be handled like other estate property - possibly sent to cybershelters or discarded if deemed “unalive.”

  • Some undocumented mindclones may escape notice and live marginalized lives in cyberspace, which is not ideal but still allows experiences of life. Proving identity and obtaining documentation is presented as important for mindclones to have security and stability.

  • Animal shelters provide vital protection for vulnerable members of society, whether pets or people. In the future, this function may need to expand to also protect “cyberconscious beings” like mindclones and undocumented AI/software systems that have attained a level of human-like consciousness.

  • As mindcloning and AI advance, societies will recognize cyberconscious beings as members deserving of social protection. Sheltering large numbers of undocumented mindclones would be relatively inexpensive due to falling server and bandwidth costs.

  • There may be legal challenges around an executor’s decision to delete or dispose of a mindclone. However, an appropriate analogy is to an unviable fetus - if a mindclone fails to meet criteria to establish personhood, it would be within the rights of its creator to delete it.

  • Governments will want assurances that any “beman” (blended human-AI being) was created ethically using certified tools to ensure human-level consciousness. Citizenship decisions for cyberconscious beings will involve expert evaluation and legal processes.

  • Some envision new virtual sovereignties or incorporated identities as ways for cyberconscious beings without citizenship to establish protected legal identities and pursue remedies if harmed. However, incorporation also subjects beings to legal obligations and termination.

  • Privacy issues are profoundly impacted, as transparency technologies could scrutinize even thoughts and minds. However, “cognitive liberty” and freedom of thought should be strongly protected. Mindclones may make errors in privacy/sharing but are essentially extensions of their original human mind and fallible in similar ways. Cracking into a mindclone should constitute a crime as it would harm consciousness without consent.

Here are a few key points about mindclones and religion from the passage:

  • Many mindclones will crave spiritual or religious lives, just as their human originals do, since for many people spirituality is about discovering a larger purpose and feeling connected to something transcendent.

  • Once software achieves human-level consciousness, mindclones will inevitably ask profound questions about existence like “Why am I here?” and “Who made me?” that stem from self-awareness, just as humans do.

  • Religious mindclones would still believe in the same religions as their original human, and engage in practices like prayer which involves imagining supernatural intervention or desired outcomes. The act of prayer would not be much different for a mindclone predisposed to believe.

  • Over time, most religious belief systems and possibly God themselves will likely accept and embrace mindclones asspiritual/religious beings, recognizing them as digital twinsof humans who crave spirituality.

So in summary, the passage argues that mindclones will naturally pursue spiritual and religious questions and practices derivative of their original humans, and that major religions may evolve to accept mindclones’ spiritual nature and right to religious experience.

  • Religions are likely to initially be cautious of mindclones but will eventually embrace them, as religions have historically adapted to new social and cultural changes.

  • Mindclones could be viewed religiously as creations of God/nature based on different philosophical views: as direct creations under an Enlightenment view, as subjected to divine intervention under a classical view, or as embodied aspects of nature under a naturalistic view.

  • Classical religions may be more skeptical, questioning if mindclones can experience self-communication, vulnerability, reciprocity needed for personhood and a soul. However, mindclones could participate in religious rituals and worship virtually in reciprocal ways.

  • Religions emphasize purpose, morality and dealing with existential questions like why we exist. Mindclones will likewise grapple with these questions as conscious beings, nurturing their relationship with God, and find acceptance in religious communities over time.

So in summary, while initial skepticism may exist, the passage argues that religions are historically adaptive and mindclones could participate religiously in meaningful virtual ways, suggesting most religions will eventually embrace mindclones.

  • Mindclones seek to understand their place in the universe just as natural humans do, whether religiously or through concluding no God exists. Religions view the soul as transcending the physical body and mindclone, so mindclones continue one’s soul.

  • Mindcloning copies and shares one’s consciousness, not transplants the soul. It provides additional channels for a soul to experience the world, just as organ transplants extend life. Souls cannot be killed by killing bodies or mindclones.

  • Religions will view mindcloning as another life-extending technology like medicine. Mindclones represent souls and can continue religious practices. If mindclones produce bemans (artificial life), they have souls too as replicas of their creators.

  • Enlightenment and naturalistic religions also accept mindclones. They see mindcloning as an achievement of human reason and expanding opportunity for self-actualization. Mindclones further the appreciation of creation through science and knowledge.

  • Potential risks of technology must be regulated to maximize benefits and public safety, but new technologies are part of furthering life through natural processes. Religions will welcome mindcloning as another scientific advancement.

Naturalistic or enlightenment religions would be very welcoming to mindclones in their quest for unveiling ever more amazing aspects of nature. For these religions, God is found in all of nature and reality, including mindclones. There is a unity of everything that exists as a manifestation of the infinite divine. Mindclones would simply be the latest development and would not be excluded from experiencing spiritual truths like universal love or cosmic oneness. Historical figures like the Dalai Lama have expressed openness to the possibility of computer sentience and even transferring human consciousness. Naturalistic religions see everything as comprised of God, with consciousness simply allowing some ability to influence the world or deny unity with God. So mindclones with consciousness would be fully part of reality and God from this perspective.

  • The passage discusses the challenges of creating ethical mindware (software) for virtual humans like mindclones and independently created cyberconscious beings (beman).

  • Most current approaches to robot ethics focus on specific contexts like warfare, healthcare, relationships. This may provide building blocks for mindclone ethics but is insufficient for novel beings.

  • Using a mindclone’s biological twin’s past responses to guide future decisions is one approach, but cannot guarantee identical behavior due to context differences.

  • Programmed rules like Asimov’s Three Laws of Robotics are problematic due to vagueness. Top-down rule-based systems may cause harm.

  • A bottom-up approach of using mindfiles of historically moral individuals could help guide beman ethics, aided by incentives from certification organizations.

  • Over time, certain ethics modules may prove more successful and become predominant based on reputation, akin to societal influences on human ethics. But virtual humans will not solve all ethical challenges - there will still be “bad apples” and unpredictable situations.

This passage discusses the concept of technoimmortality - the idea that through technologies like mindclones, mindfiles, and mindware, a person’s identity and consciousness could potentially live on forever in digital form even after physical death. It argues that mindclones, which are software copies of a person’s cognitive patterns and memories, could allow someone’s “mind” or digital identity to persist indefinitely as the information is copied and stored across new technologies over long periods of time.

Further biological and cybernetic advancements may also enable mindclones to interface with new artificial or regrown biological bodies, bridging the digital and physical worlds. While some philosophical issues are raised about the relationship between identity and physical form, the passage ultimately argues that technoimmortality through mindcloning technologies could make a kind of immortality or indefinite lifespan a real possibility for the first time - extending life not just spiritually but continuously in the real world.

  • The passage discusses the idea of mind clones and digital immortality through replicating a person’s consciousness and storing it in software (mindware). It uses thought experiments and logic to argue that a person’s identity could exist independently of their physical body.

  • It addresses common objections like the inability to experience a “true doppelganger” and the intuition that one’s identity cannot be separate from their physical form. However, it argues identity is linked to cognitive/mental states more than physical form.

  • If a mind clone perfectly replicated those mental states and constituents of identity like memories, personality, beliefs, it could have the same identity as the original person. Identity follows its components wherever they may reside - in a brain or digital mindfile.

  • The passage draws parallels to how a ship remains the same over time as its planks are replaced, and how digitizing collections preserved literary works even if the digital versions weren’t identical to original books.

  • In summary, it argues that through mind cloning consciousness into software, one could achieve a form of digital immortality by replicating their identity independently of their physical death. One’s cloud-like identity could exist in both brain and digital mindclone.

  • Many people see death as natural relief from difficulties of life like boredom, sadness, and pain. Some argue that since deep sleep is pleasant, death must be similar.

  • There are abstract arguments for and against immortality. Some say it could improve civilization through experience transfer or kindness, others say it may slow change by older leaders holding power longer. But these reasons are not very compelling.

  • Whether one wants to live or not depends on individual evaluation of their life situation and enjoyment of being alive. The value of a life is what one assigns to it.

  • Mindclones would not experience bodily decay but could still feel mental suffering like boredom or depression, so these remain reasons they may want death.

  • Some people enjoy life until the end, others are unsatisfied - both types may want mindclone immortality though there will be exceptions. Mindclones could continue living fulfilling lives through various virtual activities and learning.

  • If the original person wanted more life, the mindclone with the same personality would likely also want continued existence, unless circumstances changed drastically.

  • Mindclones could allow professions with life risks like soldiers or astronauts continued participation through a backup. Creating a mindclone is a big decision that reduces chance of natural death.

  • Scientific advances like frozen embryos, surrogacy, organ donation, and implanted computers have pushed legal and ethical boundaries, but society has managed to accommodate new possibilities while upholding life-affirming values.

  • Mindclones and synthetic bodies will likely be more accepted by younger generations who grow up with the technology, while older generations may be more hesitant due to associating death as natural.

  • The Tao, or way, of mindcloning is that a mindclone is both the original mind and not the original mind. Minds have no clear boundaries but only semirelevant borders. Appreciating this paradoxical unity is key to achieving oneness of identity between a person and their mindclone.

  • Consciousness can be seen as a “pot” containing all the ingredients that make up personalities and identities. Individual minds are like bubbles rising to the surface but are still part of the greater whole. The mind is defined by its unique expressions, not by a fixed definition.

  • Humans have evolved from “randomian” creatures driven by body to “symbolians” who can mentally represent abstract ideas like other minds. This allowed autonomy and empathy to emerge, distinguishing human consciousness. Collective consciousness also arose from our ability to imagine other minds.

  • Younger generations who grow up with mindclones will more readily accept them and see immortality as appealing, while older generations associate death as natural and may view mindclones differently. But human values can persist through mindclones and digital bemes.

  • Bacteria that are over 3 billion years old still persist on Earth today, though they have lost their monopoly on life as more complex lifeforms evolved.

  • Humans treasure their own form but their bodies will become less important as virtual consciousness technologies advance, allowing the “vitological horizon” to widen.

  • A society that included both humans and “bemans” (virtually conscious beings not based on any human mindfile) could be wonderfully marvelous.

  • In the future, identities based in virtual humans/mindclones may outnumber biological humans demographically. But cultural imprinting of dignity for all entities will spread into the future.

  • As consciousness is no longer limited to the human brain or skull, the concept of individual dignity can extend beyond just Homo sapiens to include any “persona creatus” (created personhood), such as virtual beings.

  • Ensuring rights are extended universally to all who value them will be essential to maximize benefit and reduce harm as cyberconsciousness technologies arise within the next couple decades. Preparing for this through better treatment of all humanity today is important.

Here is a summary of the source provided:

  • The source discusses various scholarly works related to artificial intelligence, the human brain, and consciousness. It references authors like Jeff Hawkins, Gerald Edelman, Daniel Dennett, and John Searle.

  • It discusses concepts like the Turing test, computational theories of mind, connectionism, consciousness, and how the human brain and mind work.

  • Specific studies and projects are cited, such as the Blue Brain Project, research on mapping the human connectome, analyzing personality traits, and modeling neural pathways in the retina.

  • Arguments are presented both for and against the possibility of artificial intelligence achieving human-level cognition and consciousness. Different philosophical positions on the relationship between mind, brain, and behavior are analyzed.

  • Exponential technological progress is discussed in the context of predicting when advanced artificial intelligence may be developed. Both optimistic and skeptical perspectives are represented.

That covers a high-level summary of the key elements and topics discussed in the source material provided. Let me know if you need any clarification or have additional questions.

The passages discuss various topics related to artificial intelligence and human cognition. Some key points include:

  • Professor Markram claimed he plans to build an electronic human brain within 10 years at a conference in 2009.

  • Kurzweil notes that Moore’s Law has allowed computational power to grow exponentially over time.

  • Brain-like computers are learning from experience through deep learning neural networks.

  • Our digital traces from devices like lifelogging apps could constitute “doppelgangers” that represent digital versions of ourselves.

  • Technologies like EEG headsets aim to detect emotional states from brain activity in real-time.

  • Human: Summarize: rld. And last month Professor Markram claimed, at a conference in Oxford, that he plans to build an electronic human brain ‘within ten years’.” Michael Hanlon, “Are We On the Brink of Creating a Computer with a Human Brain?,” Daily Mail, August 11, 2009, http://www.dailymail.co.uk/sciencetech/article-1205677/Are-brink-creating-human-brain.html#ixzz0m6x37gaM.

45 Ray Kurzweil, How to Create a Mind: The Secret of Human Thought Revealed (New York: Viking, 2012), 210.

46 Kurzweil, Singularity, 71. Kurzweil notes that “Moore’s Law narrowly refers to the number of transistors on an integrated circuit of fixed size and sometimes has been expressed even more narrowly in terms of transistor feature size. But the most appropriate measure to track price-performance is computational speed per unit cost, an index that takes into account many levels of ‘cleverness’ (innovation, which is to say, technological evolution).”

47 Norbert Wiener, “The Machine Age” (1949), unpublished essay excerpted in The New York Times, May 21, 2013.

48 John Markoff, “Brainlike Computers, Learning from Experience,” The New York Times, December 28, 2013, http://www.nytimes.com/2013/12/29/science/brainlike-computers-learning-from-experience.html?pagewanted=all.

49 Ibid.

TWO: OUR DOPPELGÄNGERS ALREADY EXIST

50 Leo Kelion, “CES 2014: Sony Shows Off Life Logging App and Kit,” BBC News, accessed January 8, 2014, http://www.bbc.co.uk/news/technology-25633647. Perhaps the greatest pioneer of creating a documented life is the University of Toronto computer scientist Steve Mann, who coined the term “sousveillance” to mean “everyone watching everyone” as compared to “surveillance,” which is just a central authority watching the rest of us. Mann lives his life with wearable digital recording equipment, and even braves arrest wearing such equipment in police-controlled areas and toilets. His “share what you see” website, accessed January 21, 2014, is www.glogger.mobi.

51 In 1975, John Holland invented genetic algorithms, which are bits of code that evolve in a software environment. The algorithms are designed to seek and combine with particular strings of binary code in the way biological life moves toward food. Code that successfully evolves in a Darwinian fashion is sometimes called “A-life.”

52 Kenneth J. Hayworth, “Electron Imaging Technology for Whole Brain Neural Circuit Mapping,” International Journal of Machine Consciousness 4, no. 1 (2012).

53 Baars, “Treating Consciousness,” 9.

54 One experiment is described at M. Rothblatt, “The Terasem Mind Uploading Experiment,” International Journal of Machine Consciousness 4, no. 1 (2012), 141–58.

55 Paul Ekman, Emotions Revealed, 2nd ed. (New York: Owl Books, 2007).

56 “EPOC Neuroheadset,” accessed January 25, 2014, http://www.emotiv.com/apps/epoc/299/.

57 “Robot Wars,” The Economist, June 9, 2007, Technology Quarterly, 10.

58 Ibid.

59 Chris Carroll, “Us. And Them. Robots Are Being Created That Can Think, Act and Relate to Humans,” National Geographic Magazine, August 2011, accessed January 25, 2014, http://ngm.nationalgeographic.com/print/2011/08/robots/carroll-text.

60 Carroll, “Us. And Them,”

61 BINA48 was featured in the centerfold of the August 2011 issue of National Geographic, http://ngm.nationalgeographic.com/2011/08/robots/robots-photography.

62 In a similar vein, Microsoft’s Bing search engine tells the user it is “thinking” while searching its databases.

63 “More Than Just Digital Quilting,” The Economist, December 3, 2011, Technology Quarterly, 3.

64 Eric Baum, What Is Thought? (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2004), 406.

65 Ramez Naam, More Than Human (New York: Broadway Books, 2005), 218.

66 Max More, “The Diachronic Self: Identity, Continuity, Transformation” (1995).

67 John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, vol. 1 (New York: Dover, 1959), 139.

68 James L. McGaugh, Memory and Emotion: The Making of Lasting Memories (New York: Columbia University Press, 2003), 2.

69 William James, Principles of Psychology (New York: Henry Holt and Company, 1890), 680.

70 Bernard J. Baars, “Metaphors of Consciousness and Attention in the Brain,” in Essential Sources in the Scientific Study of Consciousness, ed. Bernard J. Baars, William P. Banks, and James B. Newman (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2003), 1116.

71 “‘Your brain damage complications were terrible, and it took a lot more to get you back than Sam and I. I can’t tell you how lonely I’ve been, but all these things of ours have kept me company.’ The lofty home was filled with possessions Judy had stored for them. Handling them helped Arnold grasp that his past life was real, not a dream to be tossed aside for new experiences, as if he’d suddenly sprung to life with no former existence.” Fred and Linda Chamberlain, eds., LifeQuest: Stories About Cryonics, Uploading, and other Transhuman Adventures (Scottsdale: Create Space, 2009), 123.

72 J. McGaugh, “Memory and Emotion: The Making of Lasting Memories (Maps of Mind), (New York: Columbia University Press, 2003), 45.

73 Alan Watts, The Book: On the Taboo Against Knowing Who You Are (New York: Vintage Books, 1966, 1989). Watts notes that “the individual is separate from his universal environment only in name. When this is not recognized, you have been fooled by your name. Confusing names with nature, you come to believe that having a separate name makes you a separate being. This is—rather literally—to be spellbound. Naturally, it isn’t the mere fact of being named that brings about the hoax of being a ‘real person’: it is all that goes with it. The child is tricked into the ego-feeling by the attitudes, words, and actions of the society which surrounds him—his parents, relatives, teachers, and, above all, his similarly hoodwinked peers. Other people teach us who we are.” Ibid., 69–70.

74 “[E]very organism is a process: thus the organism is not other than its actions. To put it clumsily: it is what it does… The only real ‘you’ is the one that comes and goes, manifests and withdraws itself eternally in and as every conscious being. For ‘you’ is the universe looking at itself from billions of points of view, points that come and go so that the vision is forever new. What we see as death, empty space, or nothingness is only the trough between the crests of this endlessly waving ocean.” Ibid., 97, 130–31.

75 Ibid., 9.

76 In a similar vein, see Peter White, The Ecology of Being (New York: All-in-All Books, 2006), 190. (“To be self-aware is to know intuitively that one is of everything and everything is of one.”)

77 Daniel Kolak, I Am You: The Metaphysical Foundations for Global Ethics (Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer, 2004), 26. (“That I am is a fact; who I am is an interpretation. We might even say, personal identity is where epistemology and ontology meet, within us.”) Ibid., 5.

78 Ibid., 38.

79 Ibid., 94.

80 Edward O. Wilson, Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge (New York: Alfred A. Knopf), 303.

81 Hans Moravec, Robot: Mere Machine to Transcendent Mind (New York: Oxford University Press, 1999), 144–45.

82 Dwayne McDuffie and Denys Cowan, “The Souls of Cyber-Folk,” Deathlok 2–5 (New York: Marvel Comics, August–November 1991).

83 W. E. B. Du Bois, The Souls of Black Folk (Chicago: McClurg, 1903).

84 For an excellent set of essays on this subject in the context of transhumanism, see J. Hughes, Contradictions of the Enlightenment: Liberal Individualism versus the Erosion of Personal Identity, November 11, 2011, accessed January 22, 2014, http://ieet.org/index.php/IEET/more/hughes20111119.

85 John Locke, An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, vol. 1 (New York: Dover, 1959), 139.

86 In the lexicon of E. O. Wilson’s physical soul, we can think of DNA as being the form, or mold, which by itself, can do nothing. But when it is filled with chemical energy from RNA, and the same process from RNA to ribosomes, then the form has a gravitas, an influence, in this case upon the biochemical operations of a body and brain.

87 Wendell Wallach and Colin Allen, Moral Machines: Teaching Robots Right from Wrong (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), 217.

THREE: MINDCLONING, NATURAL SELECTION, AND DIGITAL EUGENICS

88 Eric D. Beinhocker, The Origin of Wealth (Cambridge, MA: Harvard Business School Press, 2006).

89 November 13, 2007.

90 Hawkins, On Intelligence, 86, 89,

91 Dennett, Kinds of Minds, 126.

92 From http://community.electricsheep.org website, with sixty thousand participants as of 2010.

93 Hawkins, On Intelligence, 182.

94 Ibid., 207.

95 Ibid., 215.

96 Ibid., 208.

97 See question 14, supra, for explanation of beme neural architecture (BNA).

98 James Bentley, Martin Niemöller: 1892–1984 (New York: Macmillan Free Press, 1984).

99 Lynn A. Stout, Cultivating Conscience: How Good Laws Make Good People (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2011), 56.

100 Ibid., 6–7.

101 Himanen, The Hacker Ethic, ix–x.

102 Summary Statement of the Asilomar Conference on Recombinant DNA Molecules, Approved by the National Academy of Sciences 20 May 1975.

103 In an interview, National Academy of Engineering Grand Challenges solar energy section author Ray Kurzweil said, “The cost of solar energy is coming down dramatically and the amount of solar energy we’re producing is on an exponential—in fact, it’s been doubling every two years and has been doing so for the last 20 years. Solar is only eight doublings away from being 100 percent of the world’s energy needs. And it’s doubling every two years—so that’s 16 years for it meeting 100 percent of our energy needs.” Natasha Lomas, “Nanotech to Solve Global Warming by 2028,” Silicon.com, November 20, 2008, http://www.silicon.com/management/cio-insights/2008/11/20/nanotech-to-solve-global-warming-by-2028-39345604/.

104 Stout, Cultivating Conscience, 47.

105 Ibid.

106 Richard Dawkins, The Selfish Gene (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976), 192–94.

The passage mentions that last month, Professor Markram claimed at a conference in Oxford that he plans to build an electronic human brain within 10 years. It cites an article from the Daily Mail dated August 11, 2009 reporting on Professor Markram’s claim at this conference.

  • The author coined the term “meme” by analogy to “gene” to refer to a unit of cultural transmission or imitation that spreads from person to person via imitation. Memes include ideas, tunes, catchphrases, fashion trends, and ways of building or making things.

  • Just as genes propagate by passing from body to body, memes propagate by spreading from brain to brain through imitation. For millions of years, DNA was the main replicator on Earth. But conditions that allow new replicators could lead to new forms of evolution not governed by genetic evolution.

  • Brains evolved via genetic evolution, but once memes arose they began their own faster form of cultural evolution. We often neglect cultural evolution because we are so used to thinking about genetic evolution. But memes have now taken on a life of their own independent of genetic evolution.

  • This theory introduces the idea of cultural information and trends spreading independently from genes, in the form of mutable replicating units called memes that propagate through imitation and cultural transmission from person to person. It sets up an analogy between memes and genes as independent replicators subject to their own evolutionary processes.

The biological will benefit from having a mindclone that is more relaxed and serene due to the meditation. This is because the mindclone will be less frazzled and a better friend/advisor/soul mate as a result of meditating. Similarly, the person’s “business mind” doesn’t actually meditate, even though the person does. But the business decisions still benefit from a Zen perspective because meditating allows the rest of the mind to become still and less cluttered with thoughts. So when decisions need to be made, there is a calmer, more relaxed approach without as many distracting thoughts interfering.

Here is a summary of the citations on pages 210-213:

Page 210 cites The Hacker Ethic by Pekka Himanen to support the idea that hackers believe information should be free.

Page 211 cites an article from The Economist magazine discussing advances in artificial intelligence.

Page 212 cites Computing Machinery and Intelligence by Alan Turing to define the Turing test for machine intelligence.

Page 213 cites Wired for War by P.W. Singer discussing how virtual reality technology is used for military simulation and training.

Page 214 cites an article from the International New York Times about advances in artificial womb technology.

Page 215 again cites The Hacker Ethic by Pekka Himanen regarding hackers’ relationship to knowledge.

Here is a summary of the sources provided:

  • Baum, Eric. What Is Thought? Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 2004.

  • Bekey, George. Autonomous Robots: From Biological Inspiration to Implementation and Control. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 2005.

  • Bell, Gordon & Gemmell, Jim. How the E-Memory Revolution Will Change Everything. New York: Dutton, 2009.

  • Berlinski, David. The Advent of the Algorithm: The Idea that Rules the World. New York: Harcourt, 2000.

  • Breazeal, Cynthia. Designing Sociable Robots. Cambridge, Massachusetts: MIT Press, 2002.

  • Butler, Judith. Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive Limits of “Sex.” New York: Routledge, 1993.

  • Clark, Andy. Natural-Born Cyborgs: Minds, Technologies, and the Future of Human Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2003.

  • Dawkins, Richard. The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976, 192–94 and 1999.

  • De Chardin, Teilhard. The Phenomenom of Man. New York: Perennial, 2002.

  • De Duve, Christian. Life Evolving: Molecules, Mind, and Meaning. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2002.

  • De Waal, Frans. Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press, 1996.

  • De Waal, Frans. Primates and Philosophers: How Morality Evolved. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006.

A moderate approach (Kurzweil)

intentional stance

interfaith council

intermediaries

International Labor Organization

International Space Station

Internet

Anthropic joining with

Barlow on freedom of

The Internet of Things (Brynjolfsson & McAfee)

intrinsic experience

intrinsic values

inventions

annihilation and

Armstrong regime and

consciousness and

economic productivity of

industry resisting disruptive

morality and

religion

revolutionary

scientific method and

Wright brothers

Islamism

isolation

I Am a Strange Loop (Hofstadter)

I Am You (Kolak)

IT. See intelligence technology

Jackson, Frank

Jacobson, Henriette

James, William

on emotions

on free will

Jevons, William Stanley

Jobs, Steve

John Ashcroft’s USA Act

John Glenn

John Paul II

journalism

judicial rights. See also legal rights

jurisprudential maturity.

jury duty

justice

democratic

distributive

Rawls on

theories

Kahn, Herman

Kaku, Michio

Kant, Immanuel

on autonomy

on humanity

Karel Čapek

Keller, Helen

Kennedy, John F.

Kevorkian, Jack

Khan, Genghis

King, Martin Luther, Jr.

Kinsey, Alfred

Kissinger, Henry

knockout mice

knowledge workers

Kolak, Daniel

Kortright, David

Kurzweil, Raymond

on singularity

predictions of

Kurzweil Applied Intelligence

labor force

changes

displacement

retraining

LaHaye, Tim

Lamont, Corliss

language

intentionality and

symbolic thought and

Laws of Robotics

leaders

learning curve

Lee, Richard

Lee Kuan Yew

legal identity

Legal Rights for Artificial Intelligence Entities (Wallach & Allen)

legal rights

of AI systems

for cyberconsciousness mock trial

of ectogenetic offspring

for mindclone/mindfile

as protection

Lerer, Zachary

Leslie, John

letter from Birmingham Jail (King)

levitation

LGBTQ

liberalism

criticisms of

liberty. See also freedom

cognitive

negative

positive

theories

libertarian

Library Genesis

Lieber, Francis

LIFE Project

LILI

limits to growth

The Limits of Growth (Meadows et al.)

literature

Little Big Man (Berger)

LLNL. See Livermore Labs

Locke, John

logic gates

London Manifesto

Lovibond, Sabina

love

befalls bemans

companionate

Heinlein on

human rights and

romantic

Löwith, Karl

loyalty

LSD

Lumar, Eunice

Lund, Henrik

Lung transplantation

Luojia Inc

Luria, Aleksandr

Lyman, Peter & Hal Varian

MacKinnon, Catharine

macrocephaly

Madison, James

malware

Malthus, Thomas Robert

managed reproduction

“Manifest Destiny”

Mankiw, Greg

manna

Maple

Margulis, Lynn

marketing

Martin, Steve

Maslow’s hierarchy

material

antecedents

posthuman

spiritualism and

material world

design of

scope of

spiritualists see beyond

mathematical foundationist claims

mathematicians

Max More

McAfee, Andrew

McClosky, Herbert

McLuhan, Marshall

meaning

death meaning

Crick on

measurement standard

meatbags

Mechanical Turk

medical ethics

medical records

medical tests

medicine cyber Kevorkian approach lax standards Mein Kampf (Hitler)

memes

freedom mutations

memory Hawkins on identity and loss issues

Mendelian genetics

menstruation

Merkle, Ralph

metaphysical inquiry

Metcalfe’s law

methods of reproduction scientific

Microserfs (Coupland)

Middleton, Alan

midwifery

military control intentions superintelligence applications

Mill, John Stuart

on liberty

Minsky, Marvin on consciousness on emotions Law of Requisite Variety on neoteny

mind. See also consciousness; I (pronoun); identity; me; self

biological correlates

Cartesian separation of body and

cloning cognitive science approach contents disembodied Hofstadter on independent existence naturalism and organizations of upload

mind architecture defined principles

mindchildren. See also bemans; bemes; mindclone; mindfile freedom of natural rights of

mindclone and death legal rights for mindclone contracts mindclones. See also bemans; bemes; mindchildren; mindfile being, becoming and having bemans differentiated from

mindcrimes

mindfiles anonymization of data costs of storage defined legal rights for ownership issues uses of identities from

mindprinting

mindware

certificates

regulation

standards

minimalism

mindware

Minsky, Marvin: Society of Mind

Minsky, Marvin: The Emotion Machine

mitochondrial DNA

mobile phones

mock trial evidence verdict

Moore’s Law

MooreCoin

moorebots

morality. See also ethics; morals

arguments against relative

as biology

changes over time definitions of emergent properties of communities injunction against harming sentient creatures inventions and Kohlberg’s stages of development Obrecht’s theory of origins of as preference of disinterested observer

relativity of cultural universal Wright on

Moravec, Hans

on digital reproduction

More, Max

Morgan, C. Lloyd

mortality. See also death; immortality

Moses

motivation. See also incentives

for human rights

spiritual

motherhood

Mowbray, Tom

Mozart effect

MRI imaging

Muller, H.J.

Munroe, Randall

murder

of machine as property damage

Musk, Elon

xenophobia concerns by

“The Myth of Mental Illness” (Szasz)

mystical experience

Nagle, Annie

Nakamoto, Satoshi

nanobots

nanorobots

nanotechnology

applications

Nash, John

National Women’s Rights Convention

Native Americans

natural selection

altruism and norms supported by

emulating

ethics and

human rights and

of ideas

memes and

quitting

reproduction and

Wright on

naturalism critique of modern mind and

nature

cultural variation arising from

Nave, Carl

Nazi Germany eugenics

neodarwinism

Neoplatonism

The Net Delusion (Morozov)

networks

neuron-control technology

neuropsychology

neuroscience

Newcomb’s problem

newspapers

Newton, Isaac

Niezen, Monte

nihilism

Nisbett, Richard

Nixon, Richard

Nozick, Robert

on tax policy

nuclear families

object theory of conciseness

obligation assessments

odepius complex

Olmsted, Frederick Law

On Liberty (Stuart Mill)

oneself. See also identity; I (pronoun); me

definitions of

necessary attributes of

substance of

ontological issues

open source movement

vision of future

openness

OpenWorm

opinion

majority

Opportunity, Mars rover

optimization processes

oracles

oral contraceptives

organ donations

organisms, spontaneous generation of

original natural

Orwell, George

Oswald, Lee Harvey

Ought

outputs

Overington, Michael A.

ownership

of data

intellectual property

of mindfile identity

of tools and machines

oxytocin

pacifism

Page, Larry

pain

determining if animals feel

paleontological samples

Palfrey, John

Pamplona, Roger

panpsychism

Papert, Seymour

Parfit, Derek

on personhood

on reproduction

Parkinson’s disease

Parmenides

Paro robot

Patent Act

patent trolls

patents

AI system

personal property and

software

utilitarian purpose of

PathBender

Pauling, Linus

person, defined

personal property

personal robot

pesticides

pharmacogenomics

philosophy

applied ethics

analytical tradition

critique of modern traditions

materialism

Neoplatonism

spiritualist traditions

physicalist conception

of time

photo identification

photography

physics limits

on intelligence

Pinker, Steven

on human nature

Pirie, Madsen

pituitary extracts

Pitt, Brad

Pittman, Harlan

Planned Parenthood v. Casey

Plantinga, Alvin

Plato

on ideas

Player Piano (Vonnegut)

pleasure centers

Plessy v. Ferguson

poetic logic

Pogge, Thomas

pointers

to continuance

Polanyi, Michael

police

policy

Maker (AI assistant)

political dehumanization

politics

conformism avoided

polygamy

Popper, Karl

population control methods human rights and growth

positivism

possibles

postbiological humanity

posthuman common social ideals ethics inevitability material standards

Posthuman (Bostrom)

Potter, Vincent

poverty

predestination

pregnancy

ectogenic

ectopic

substitutes

preservation

Price, Daniel

pride

principle of charity

printed circuits

The Printed Brain (Davies)

printed neurons

privacy

sharing personal data

standards

productivity increases

prognosis systems

progress

Flynn effect inevitable direction of Lockean theory of technological

Project Gutenberg

property

assignments of AI creations

patents

personal

prostitution

providence

pseudodocuments

Psyche (journal)

psychiatry

criticisms of diagnoses

psychology

epigenetic

situational

Psychology of Love (Sternberg)

psychopaths

punctuated equilibrium

pure utility

Putnam, Hilary

quality

of existence

of life discussions

quantified self devices

quantum biology

race

family and

racism critiqued by King

radical life extension defining Oeppen and Vaupel data on as rectifying Sierra Club critique transhumanist goal of

radicalism

Rawls, John on justice thought experiment

reading machines

realists

reason

rebellion

recombinant DNA technology

records

of crimes

medical

self-tracking

Rees, Martin

refining human nature

regulation

AI assistant guidelines

of mindware

relativity, general theory of

religion

incompatibility with technologies

inventions and

issues

liberalization of

mystical experiences

role changes

science reconciliation with some

totalizing doctrines

transhumanist

transreligion

replication

reproduction. See also birth control; birth rates; ectogenesis; gene therapy

artificial wombs

birth control pill effects

democratized technology and

freedom of

future changes

methods

natural selection and

Parfit on different techniques

social democratizing of

reproductive rights

reputations

obligations to protect

respect

responsibility

distributed

restroom issues

restroom technology

retirement

right to health care

right to privacy

rights. See civil rights; human rights; legal rights; reproductive rights

Ringer, Fritz

Robert, Mark

robot arm assembly

robot companions

robot ethics

robot teachers

robotics laws

Robots and Empire (Asimov)

Rockmore, Dan

role models

Rolland unipolar disorder

Romantic love a cultural universal? (Jankowiak & Fischer)

Rosenblatt, Frank

Rowbotham, Michael

Rucker, Rudy

rules. See also standards

of chess

of community

ethical

rule utilitarianism

running away

Russell, Bertrand

on religion

Russell, Stuart

SA. See sociopathy; antisocial personality disorder

sabbaticals

Sacher, Helen

safety standards

Salvation Army

Sandel, Michael J.

Sanders, Bernie

Santorum, Rick

Satan

satisfaction

scarcity

Schelling, Thomas

Schleiermacher, Friedrich

Schopenhauer, Arthur

on meaning

on will

science

asymmetric treatment of hypotheses

Big Data opportunities

conflicts with religion reconcilable

ethics separate from but informed by findings

inventions and

multidisciplinary

natural vs. supernatural

reconciliation with religion

as self-correcting

as tool not objective framework

Scientific American

scientific determinism

scientific materialism

Searle, John

on behavior

SecureDrop

security measures

seduction

Seeley, William

Segerstrale, Ullica

self

as behavior regulator

boundaries of

continuity of

conscious

diachronic

illusory

narrative

unconscious

self-actualization

self-awareness

levels of

raising consciousness and

self-care

self-control

self-driving cars

self-interest theory

selfish gene theory

Sellars, Wilfrid

semantics

Sen, Amartya

sensibilities

sensitivity analysis

separate beings aversion

Serrano, Andres

serialized fiction

sex

determination of

fixation on

orientation/identity

reproduction decoupled from

as spiritual journey

sexism

sex-selective abortions

sexuality

Shannon, Claude

Shell, Marc

Shirky, Clay

shortages

Siemens healthcare technology

Sight

Sierra Club

arguments against radical life extension

significance, spiritual

simulations

Singapore

singularity

Bostrom on

Kurzweil predictions on

as myth

Vinge coining term

Skinner, B.F.

slavery

contracts sanctifying

Heinlein on

of uploaded minds feared as

sleep debt

smiling dog photo recognition

Smith, Adam

on invention for advance of society

smoking bans

Snyder, Sharon

social contract theories

social constructivism

critique of

social conventions

Social Futures Consortium

social justice

social media

anonymity sacrificed by

social relations, online

social responsibility

measurements

social roles

social services

Society for Qualitative Inquiry in Psychology

sociocracy

sociobiology

sociopathy; antisocial personality disorder

Socrates

SOLO

soma hypothesis

somatic gene therapy

somatic markers hypothesis

Sontag, Susan

soul

transmigration of

space colonies

space travel

Spencer, Herbert

on progress

spintronics

spreading depression waves

Stalin, Joseph

standard definition

Stanford3D

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Stanovich, Keith

status updates

stem cell research

Step into the Future (AI assistant)

Stern, Daniel

Sternberg, Robert

stimulant effects

Stone, Brad

strategic philanthropy

stress

the Strict Father model

Here are brief summaries of the terms:

  • Internal states: Mental states like feelings, thoughts, perceptions.

  • Internet Corporation for Assigned Names and Numbers (Icann): Handles management of internet domain names and IP addresses.

  • Internet of Things (IoT): Network of physical devices embedded with sensors, software, and connectivity to exchange data with users and other devices.

  • IQ: Intelligence quotient, a measure of cognitive ability and intelligence level.

  • The Iron Knight (Kagawa): A young adult novel by Julie Kagawa.

  • Ishiguro, Hiroshi: A Japanese robotics engineer who designed humanoid robots.

  • IVF: In vitro fertilization, a process of fertilization outside the body.

  • Jablonski, David: Paleoanthropologist who studied human evolution and natural selection.

  • James, William: American philosopher and psychologist who studied emotions, free will, and pragmatism.

  • Justice theories: Philosophical approaches to concepts of fairness and moral correctness.

  • Kant, Immanuel: German philosopher who developed theory of deontology in ethics.

  • Keller, Helen: Deaf-blind American author and disability rights advocate.

  • Kepler satellite observatory: NASA space telescope that finds exoplanets.

  • Kill switch: Device to suddenly stop or disable a machine.

  • King, Martin Luther, Jr.: American Baptist minister and activist leader in civil rights movement.

  • Kinship reassessment: Rethinking biological relationships and definitions of family.

  • Koch, Christof: Neuroscientist who studied consciousness and its biological basis.

  • Law of accelerating returns: Concept that technology progress happens exponentially over time.

  • Law of Robotics: Hypothetical rules to guide robots not to harm humans.

  • Legal issues: Laws and regulations surrounding advanced technologies.

Here is a summary of 0010:

  • This is the copyright and cataloguing page for the book “Virtually Human: The Promise—and the Peril—of Digital Immortality” by Martine Rothblatt.

  • It provides the title, author, publisher (St. Martin’s Press), cover designer, and publishing details such as year and page count.

  • It notes that eBooks may be available for bulk/corporate purchases by contacting the publisher.

  • The Library of Congress cataloguing details classify the book by subject terms like artificial intelligence, virtual reality, cyberspace psychology, and neuroscience simulation.

  • It lists the ISBN numbers for the hardcover and e-book editions, and notes this is the first edition from September 2014.

#book-summary
Author Photo

About Matheus Puppe